The long-suffering Muse of History
- June 3, 2024
- Armand D'Angour
- Themes: Classics
Theoretical approaches only get ancient scholars so far in the quest for historical truths.
The Muse of History: The Ancient Greeks From the Enlightenment to the Present, Oswyn Murray, Allen Lane, £30
Students of ancient history at Oxford in the 1970s and 1980s, as I was, attended Oswyn Murray’s lectures with pleasure and appreciation (another such was, somewhat later, the former PM Boris Johnson, to whom Murray sent a formal renunciation of friendship after Brexit). Murray communicated ancient Greek history with infectious enjoyment, bringing to it a range of sources and approaches that enlivened the subject. His affable demeanour made him unusually approachable, and his eminence as a pedagogue was confirmed when his Early Greece, published in 1980 (now in a second edition from 1993), became an instant favourite among students of classics and ancient history. Now in his late 80s and ever youthful in demeanour, Murray can surely claim to be included in the pantheon of ancient historians whose life and work span the period ‘from the Enlightenment to the Present’.
This informative and accessibly written book confirms that claim. ‘At a certain point,’ we read, ‘one wakes up to discover that one has become truly an “ancient historian”… a part of history itself.’ Murray continues in autobiographical mode: ‘I was born in 1937…’ (‘History will be kind to me’, Churchill is quoted as saying, ‘for I intend to write it.’) Scattered throughout the book are personal accounts of the author’s discoveries and insights, along with first-hand reminiscences of such figures as his mentor, the Italian historian Arnaldo Momigliano, and his friend, the Czech academic Pavel Oliva. The books of the latter historians are still widely consulted; few will be equally familiar with Temple Stanyan, author of ‘the first substantial narrative history of Greece’, or with the writings of such historians as Charles Rollin, J.-J. Barthélemy, Cornelius de Pauw, and other 18th- and 19th-century historians to whose work Murray presents himself as an informative guide.
‘The present’ will have caused more problems of selection than the past. Murray’s attention to close personal acquaintances risks eliding the considerable contributions of eminent contemporaries less well known to him, many of whom go unmentioned. Of recent Oxford-based historians of ancient Greece such as George Cawkwell, George Forrest, David Lewis, and Russell Meiggs, and the younger generation such as Robin Lane Fox, Simon Hornblower, Peter Rhodes, and Robert Parker, only Cawkwell and Lewis are mentioned (once each and en passant). ‘Murray, Oswyn’ merits nine references in the index, but of Cambridge and other non-Oxford counterparts younger than Moses Finley, only Geoffrey Lloyd and Simon Goldhill are cited, thanks to their having acknowledged the influence of the ‘Paris school’ of historians Jean-Paul (‘Jipé’) Vernant and Pierre Vidal-Naquet. While other recent Cambridge-based luminaries go unmentioned, more regrettable is the complete absence from the account of the 20th- century French women historians Jacqueline de Romilly and Nicole Loraux, who surely stand comparison with others of their era; and the 19th_20th century Cambridge historian of religion Jane Harrison might have merited at least as much space as that given to Max Müller.
It appears that the non-theoretical stance of many British historians (and evidently North Americans, who are wholly omitted with the exception of Jipé-inspired Froma Zeitlin) might have diminished their significance in Murray’s eyes. ‘British empiricism or positivism’ he writes, ‘is based on the belief that only facts exist (whatever they may be), and that history can always be interpreted on the basis of an unreflective [sic] search for an illusory certainty contained in an explanatory system which is held to be constantly changing, yet universal in human history.’ This awkwardly condensed and unduly scathing judgment follows the assertion that ‘The European tradition of Ancient History was dominated by French philosophical interpretations of history in the eighteenth century and by systematic German scholarship in the nineteenth century. Compared with these two approaches the Anglo-Saxon tradition has lacked any theoretical or conceptual basis, with the exceptions of Utilitarian and Marxist historiography.’ We learn nonetheless of the work of the ‘robust but parochial’ William Mitford and the ‘Utilitarian’ banker George Grote, as well as the more continentally inspired novelist Bulwer-Lytton, whose writings Murray has championed along with that of the Swiss Jacob Burckhardt. (By contrast, figures such as the English-educated historian Alfred Zimmern, whose Greek Commonwealth was widely popular in its time, are absent). Yet British empiricists also had their continental counterparts. Leopold von Ranke, no less a German than Karl Marx, ‘laid claim to producing an account of history “as it really was”’ (wie es eigentlich gewesen ist); and at least, as Murray observes, ‘the school of Ranke established a permanent link between archival research and the writing of history’.
What theoretical approach, one wonders, is Murray’s own history of ancient historians itself meant to demonstrate? His ‘empirical’ expertise is why many still value his Early Greece and other contributions such as his edition of collected essays on the ancient Greek symposium. In a chapter here entitled ‘The Problem of Socrates’ we read the confident statement: ‘It is quite clear that the picture drawn by Plato in his dialogues as a whole is incompatible with the evidence of Aristophanes and Xenophon.’ In fact, Aristophanes’ picture of Socrates as a middle-aged man, though distorted for comic purposes, is far from incompatible with an understanding of Socrates the man (if not the philosopher); but Murray discusses only the idealising accounts of the older philosopher by such interpreters as Hegel, Kierkegaard, and Burckhardt. These are no less biographical fantasies than Nietzsche’s contrastingly hostile attitude to Socrates, which led to his bizarre contention that the philosopher almost single-handedly (Euripides was a fellow-culprit) destroyed the spirit of Greek tragedy.
To claim, then, that ‘Socrates is the first (indeed the only) Greek about whom it is possible to write a biography’ is strange, given that the evidence for Socrates’ earlier life and intellectual development has been routinely overlooked by such biographers; the latest Socratic biographer cited is Gregory Vlastos, and there is no place for the excellent W.K.C. Guthrie (let alone I.F. Stone, Robin Waterhouse, or Bettany Hughes). One of the most exciting findings of recent studies is the confirmation of Socrates’ early and continuing association with Pericles’ circle via his mentor Archelaus and his pupil Alcibiades, and his well-reported acquaintance with Aspasia of Miletus as portrayed in Plato’s Menexenus and arguably underlying the account of ‘Diotima’ in the Symposium. That Aspasia doesn’t merit even a footnote in this book – she was, after all, the subject of many accounts including W. S. Landor’s Pericles and Aspasia – feels like an unnecessary rebuff to the long-suffering Muse of History.
Murray begins and ends by restating the familiar premise that ‘all history is contemporary history’ (Benedetto Croce). ‘The past is a rich and varied tapestry’, Murray writes, ‘that may never be completely understood and must always be renewed, yet to approach our predecessors with due humility creates a richer interpretation than we can achieve on our own.’ In fact, no understanding of the past can but fall far short of ‘complete’; and it would be impossible to create an interpretation of history, rich or otherwise, without reference to historiographical predecessors. It therefore seems ironic that, given the above-mentioned omissions, a whole chapter is devoted to expounding the story of a ‘lost historian’, the Irish John Gast, whom virtually no one today will have heard of or read, and who caught Murray’s interest only as late as 2008. The obscurity into which Gast’s work fell as early, we are told, as 1812 makes him a curious footnote, a rose born to blush unseen, with no influence on later approaches, theoretical or otherwise, to the discipline. If future students of ancient historiography are able to acknowledge Gast as a minor star in the ancient historical firmament, it will be entirely thanks to Murray’s enthusiasm on his behalf.